Different types of synaesthetic experiences involve different brain mechanisms

SUBJECTIVE experience poses a major problem for neuroscientists and philosophers alike, and the relationship between them and brain function is particularly puzzling. How can I know that my perception of the colour red is the same as yours, when my experience of the colour occupies a private mental world to which nobody else has access? How is the sensory information from an object transformed into an experience that enters conscious awareness? The neural mechanisms involved are like a black box, whose inner workings are a complete mystery. 

In synaesthesia, the information entering one sensory system gives rise to sensations in another sensory modality. Letters can evoke colours, for example, and movements can evoke sounds. These extraordinary additional sensations therefore offer a unique opportunity to investigate how the subjective experiences of healthy people are related to brain function. Dutch psychologists now report that different types of synaesthetic experiences are associated with different brain mechanisms, providing a rare glimpse into the workings of the black box.

One of the best characterized forms of synaesthesia is grapheme-colour synaesthesia, in which seeing or hearing a particular letter or number evokes the experience of a particular colour. One well-known grapheme-colour synaesthete is the Nobel Prize-winning physicist Richard Feynman, who said, "When I see equations, I see the letters in colours." Feynman was a "projector" synaesthete - he automatically perceived the evoked colours in the external space, or "outside world". The quality of the synaesthetic experience can, however, differ markedly between individuals: in "associator" synaesthetes, the evoked colour is perceived internally, or "in the mind's eye".

Projector and associator synaesthetes are most easily distinguished from one another on the basis of their own subjective reports, but the differences between their experiences can also be measured objectively. One study showed that projectors and associators can easily be distinguished from one another by their performance on various types of Stroop tests, in which a colour word is printed in a colour that differs from the meaning of the word (e.g. RED and BLUE). When asked to name the printed colour, the discrepancy causes longer response times and more errors, because we can read words more quickly than we can name colours. Projectors take longer to respond than associators, because their synaesthetic colour experience results in more interference during the task.

Romke Rouwe and H. Steven Scholte of the University of Amsterdam now report that these different synaesthetic experiences are associated with distinct underlying brain mechanisms, and that there also are structural differences between the brains of projector and associator synaesthetes. They recruited 16 projector and 26 associator grapheme-colour synaesthetes, placed them in a brain scanner, and showed them letters and numbers to evoke synaesthetic experiences. 42 non-synaesthetic controls were also recruited, so that the researchers could look for differences in brain structure and activation patterns between the synaesthetes and controls, as well as  differences between the projectors and associators.

synaesthesia brain.JPG

The synaesthetes were found to have greater gray matter density than the non-synaesthetes in the superior posterior parietal lobe (above), and this was found to be independent of the exact nature of the synaesthetic experience. The superior parietal lobe is a region of the visual cortex which is known to be selectively activated by colours. Previous studies have shown that activity in this part of the brain is increased in synaesthesia, and that disrupting its activity diminishes the intensity of synaesthetic experiences. The superior parietal lobe is therefore closely associated with synaesthesia, and is thought to integrate (or "bind") the neural representations of colour and shape so that sensations of colour are evoked by letters or numbers.    

The scans also revealed structural and functional differences between the projectors and associators. Projectors were found to have increased gray matter density in the visual and auditory regions of the brain. Increased activation of these areas was also observed in the projectors but not in the associators or controls. This may account for the subjective experiences of projector synaesthetes - activation of the brain areas areas involved in perceiving real objects causes letters and numbers to evoke the vivid experience of colours in external space.

By contrast, associators were found to have increased gray matter in, and greater activation of, the hippocampus and surrounding areas, which are known to be critical for the formation of autobiographical, semantic and spatial memories. The synaesthetic experiences of associators, then, which are purely internal, are apparently similar to memory retrieval - letters and numbers merely evoke recollections of the experience of colours, rather than vivid impressions of the colours themselves.

Thus, the brain mechanisms underlying the experiences of projector and associator grapheme-colour synaesthetes are partly shared - both projectors and associators exhibit structural and functional differences in the superior parietal lobe when compared to non-synaesthetes. But the subjective experiences of projectors are very different from those of associators, even though the sensory stimuli stimuli that evoke the experiences are exactly the same. This is because of differences in the underlying brain mechanisms, and the properties of the experiences are wholly consistent with the observed brain activity patterns: projectors actually see colour impressions due to visual cortical activation, but associators do not because the stimuli do not evoke activity in the visual brain areas.

An interesting question raised by these findings is whether or not the observed differences between projectors and associators extend to other forms of synaesthesia. Time-space synaesthetes, for example, experience units of time as occupying specific locations around the body, and in many cases, the passage of time is associated with changes in the perspective from which this visual representation is seen. Are there also individual differences in the experiences of time-space synaesthetes and, if so, are they too associated with different underlying brain mechanisms? Further research may provide some answers.

Related:


Rouw, R., & Scholte, H. (2010). Neural Basis of Individual Differences in Synesthetic Experiences. J. Neurosci. 30: 6205-6213. DOI: 10.1523/JNEUROSCI.3444-09.2010.

Dixon, M. J., et al. (2004). Not all synaesthetes are created equal: Projector versus associator synaesthetes. Cog. Aff. Behav. Neurosci. 4: 335-343. [PDF]

More like this

In the 1880s, Francis Galton described a condition in which "persons...almost invariably think of numerals in visual imagery." This "peculiar habit of mind" is today called synaesthesia, and Galton's description clearly defines this condition as one in which stimuli of one sensory modality…
SYNAESTHESIA is a neurological condition in which there is a merging of the senses, so that activity in one sensory modality elicits sensations in another. Although first described by Francis Galton in the 1880s, little was known about this condition until recently. A rennaissance in synaesthesia…
Synaesthesia is a neurological condition in which stimuli of one sensory modality evoke experiences in another modality. This is thought to occur as a result of  insufficient "pruning" during development, so that most of the pathways connecting parts of the brain mediating the different senses…
Some people experience an intermingling of the senses, known as synaesthesia, in which certain shapes become combined or "bound with" certain colors, or that certain colors are strongly associated with certain sounds. Of course, in healthy normal adults, color and shape become bound together only…

This one looks like its defending a food source. (it seems to stick its face into the meat a few times.) ground squirrels (I know this is a tree squirrel) often cannibalize their dead, sometimes with revolting conseqences

This is interesting. I had never heard of the distinction between "projector" and "associator" synaesthesia before.

People sometimes make the case that we are all slightly synaesthesic. I am thinking this could be true of associator synaesthesia but not of projector synaesthesia.

But surely we should be modest about the results of these studies. Just because electricity pops up in certain places at certain times doesn't mean we understand actual mechanisms! I have in mind the distinction between neuroimaging and cognitive science more broadly, for example.

These discussion always begin with announcements of broad issues and projects, as does this post. But the actual scientific content is so narrow, albeit interesting.

NS

Enjoyed this blogpost. I first became aware of the phenomenon on reading Luria's Mind of a Mnemonist.

By Shirlsmor (not verified) on 08 May 2010 #permalink

I'm still trying to figure out the difference between "internally experienced colors" and "externally experienced colors" when describing an internal synesthetic experience. For me, the experience changes as I focus on it.

I've always resisted categorizing myself, but now that I see the difference can be quantified, I may need to think about it. I mean it's sort of in my mind, yet I sort of "see" the colors too, along with the words especially when I stop and think about it.

Some words cannot be experienced without associating their color, such as the names of the months where the word almost seems colored, but do I always experience the color, when reading for example? Not really. But it's always there. In my mind's eye.

This is interesting. I am a projector grapheme-color synesthete, but I might have some associated synethesia too. That's rather intriguing that they found different brain activity between projectors and associators.

Though the internal experience of color may be locked in a black box there are a number of constraints to considering the possibility that our internal color states differ markedly between one another. Nearly everyone who gives an example of a color to illustrate how our experiences are opaque to one another uses red just as you did. Red is a unique color, there is no yellow in it nor any blue, certainly no green. Of all the unique colors it is the one who's unique spectral range is limited experientially in that most observers will pick out close matches for unique red whereas the range that observers pick out for unique green is widely divergent. What you pick out for red is likely to be close to what I pick out for red but what you pick out for green might be what I call blue-greeen or yellow-green.

There are a number of other constraints on internal color states and though the experience of another may be ultimately locked in that black box, it is almost certain that they are very similar.

C.L. Hardin wrote a wonderful essay "Reinverting the Spectrum" which is in "Readings on Color: the Philosophy of Color" where he discusses and contrains this issue at great length.

By Robert Bate (not verified) on 13 May 2010 #permalink

@ Notedscholar - The interesting finding reported here is increased gray matter density (not "electricity") in the ROI. This overlaps with previous findings that this particular ROI has greater activity during synaesthetic experience but tells us that this region is structurally different (as well showing greater involvement during processing tasks during such experience). It has also been shown that there is greater white matter connectivity between ROIs that show greater activity in synaesthetic experience. If we take these ideas in conjunction with a knowledge of fundamental neuroscience we can begin to build a picture of how greater connectivity might lead to greater ROI involvement (activity) which may lead to greater grey matter density due to increased local processing during a greater number of day-to-day tasks (i.e. the colour system has developed a more generalisable function by association and/or projection). This causal chain can be probed through a series of well designed experiments. CogSci cannot continue to rebut the fact that the brain is a neural system, and that this is reflected in cognition - we are now distinctly beyond the level of functionally discrete modules.

By JTizzle36 (not verified) on 15 May 2010 #permalink