αEP: Complexity is not usually the product of selection

This is another addition to my αEP series about evolutionary psychology. Here's the first, and unfortunately there are several more to come.

By the way, people are wondering about the α in the title. Don't you people do any immunology? α is standard shorthand for "anti".

I mentioned in the last one this annoying tendency of too many pro-evolution people to cite "complexity" as a factor that supports the assertion of selection for a trait. Strangely, the intelligent design creationists also yell "Complexity!" at the drop of a hat, only it's to prove that evolution can't work.

They're both wrong.

I ran across a prime example of this recently in a post by John Wilkins (It's pick-on-John-Wilkins day! Hooray!)

Opponents, largely following Gould and Lewontin’s 1979 attack, tend to assert (often without consideration of the particular attempts to give adaptive explanations) that any and all adaptive hypotheses are cheap and to be avoided. This has the effect of basically eliminating natural selective accounts of anything. But we know that selection is the only process that results in complexity over any time, and the fact there are complex traits among organisms leads to the inevitable conclusion that we should be able to give selective explanations from time to time. I have argued before that we should think of adaptation as a viable hypothesis at all times; but being viable doesn’t make it true. The problem is not that EP or sociobiology makes adaptive hypotheses. They should. It is that they often make them without testing them.

I will concede the general point: a well-designed and testable adaptive hypothesis is a perfectly reasonable starting point to do science, and I agree that one big problem with evolutionary psychology is that most of their adaptive hypotheses are poorly done. But I've highlighted the chunk in the middle that's just absurd: complex traits are the product of selection? Come on, John, you know better than that. Even the creationists get this one right when they argue that there may not be adaptive paths that take you step by step to complex innovations, especially not paths where fitness doesn't increase incrementally at each step. Their problem is that they don't understand any other mechanisms at all well (and they don't understand selection that well, either), so they think it's an evolution-stopper — but you should know better.

This is the trap Michael Behe falls into, too. It's the assumption that you have to have an adaptive scenario for every step, and an inability to imagine non-adaptive solutions. I think if selection were always the rule, then we'd never have evolved beyond prokaryotes -- all that fancy stuff eukaryotes added just gets in the way of the one true business of evolution, reproduction.

So let's work through a hypothetical scenario of increasing complexity, and you try to see where selection is essential. And then I'll give some real world examples.

Imagine an enzyme E with with a fairly nonspecific, broad spectrum of binding for various chemical substrates. It can bind substrate A or substrate B with equal facility, and then carries out some modification of the substrate — let's say it hydrolizes some side group. We'll call this enzyme EAB for its substrates.

Now imagine a fairly common mutational event, a gene duplication. An individual in this population acquires a second copy of its gene, so now it is EAB-EAB. Is this event dependent on selection? No, obviously not.

But now this mutation spreads through the population, so a significant fraction of the individuals carry it. Is that dependent on selection?

It could be, but most likely isn't. There are situations where you might gain an advantage from having a second copy of a gene — cases where the organism is dependent on the concentration of the gene products, and the availability of the enzyme is to some degree rate-limiting. Human salivary amylase, for instance, exhibits a pattern of increasing copy number in populations with lots of starch in their diets. But you can't assume that a gene duplication is beneficial a priori; you have to do the hard work of correlating gene number with an effect.

That's because in many other cases, the duplication is going to be neutral in effect, or even deleterious. It's going to be a tiny cost in replication, for example (but negligible, because selection doesn't see very small fitness costs and replication is a small part of most cell's energy budget), and many processes are sensitive to dosage, where increases in gene number can damage the equilibrium of the cell. If this weren't true, then Down syndrome children, who carry an extra copy of a whole chromosome, would be superhuman.

So let's say that this step of the increasing frequency of a gene duplication is usually going to be the result of genetic drift, but sometimes will have an adaptive benefit…but you have to demonstrate the latter, rather than assuming it.

So now you have a population with a large subset carrying the EAB-EAB duplication. What next? Mutations can occur in either of the copies.

The most likely result is destruction of the function of one of the copies: EAB-EAB becomes EAB-X, where X is now a damaged, non-functional pseudogene. We're back to square one, except of course if you were arguing that the duplication had to incur a benefit, because now the pseudogene is nothing but cost — it incurs that neglible replication cost, but also it would be at a disadvantage relative to those individuals that carried your hypothetically advantageous duplication. But look: the human genome contains at least 12,000 pseudogenes (out of 20,000 genes), and some genes, like cytochrome C, may have 49 pseudogene copies. Most of these mutations are also going to be nearly neutral.

The interesting case, though, is where something changes in one of the copies short of actually destroying the gene. What if one loses it's broad specificity and now becomes able only to bind one of the substrates…for example, we now have an individual carrying EA-EAB. Will this variant expand through the population by selection?

Again, not likely. This individual is still processing A and B with a pair of enzymes, and any difference between it and others would be small (and probably invisible to selection, at least if it's in a messy slow breeding metazoan, for instance).

Similarly, there would be other mutations in the population: we could have mutants carrying EAB-EB, for instance, with a more specific second enzyme. We could have mutants that knock out functions in any order: X-EAB, or EB-EAB. All kinds of variants arise by chance mutation, and spread to varying degrees through the population by drift. No selection need be involved, and you get all this complexity in the population arising entirely spontaneously. And a good part of the reason that this can occur is because selection plays no role.

Things get more complex in the absence of selection. Selection, as Wilkins well understands, is generally a conservative process that removes phenotypic variation from the population (with some exceptions). It is precisely the inability of selection to cull all variants that deviate from the successful, well-tested norm that allows novel complexity to emerge.

In our hypothetical population, for instance, we have all kinds of different patterns of the E gene: we have the ancestral type, EAB, the duplicated form, EAB-EAB, forms carrying pseudogenes, X-EAB and EAB-X, and forms with subtle differences in the specificity of the enzymes, EA-EAB and EAB-EB. None of this is the product of selection. But now you can get recombination, and maybe some of those combinations will be visible to selection.

For instance, when X-EAB breeds with EAB-X, some of the progeny could be X-X, a complete knockout of the enzyme. That could be, but isn't necessarily, deleterious. You could get the particularly interesting combination EA-EB, where now what you've accomplished is the separation of two of the functions of the ancestral enzyme into two separate, more specific enzymes.

Is the condition EA-EBmore fit than the ancestral state of EAB? I would argue that usually, no, it's not. It's going to be a nearly neutral variant in that both individuals process the A and B molecules just fine. Maybe somewhere further down the road, two separate molecules to do these two functions opens the door to more flexibility and interesting new possibilities, but evolution and selection do not care about future potential, only with short term consequences.

The bottom line is that you cannot easily explain most increases in complexity with adaptationist rationales. You have to consider chance as far more important, and far more likely to produced elaborations.

Do these phenomena operate in the real world, rather than just hypothetical scenarios? Yes. For example, look at the globin genes. These are found in two clusters, an α cluster with seven genes (including two pseudogenes) and a β cluster with five genes. All the genes are related and similar and function — these are all proteins with heme and oxygen-carrying functions — where each gene has slightly different functions (one may have a higher affinity for oxygen than another) and patterns of expression (one may be expressed at a different stage of development than another, or in a different range of tissues), and we can see specific functional adaptations for each, but their origin has to be in a selectively neutral condition.

A fetal hemoglobin with a high affinity for oxygen is an adaptation when expressed in a fetus, but detrimental when expressed in a pregnant woman (it wouldn't share oxygen as readily with the fetus). The selective advantage could only arise after the different globins had evolved, and when differential gene expression mechanisms had been coupled to them to assure that they would only be expressed under appropriate conditions. The origin was not a selection event, but the refinement to specific roles probably was.

The classic example, though, is Joe Thornton's work on the step-by-step evolution of mineralocorticoid and glucocorticoid receptors from an ancestral receptor. You cannot understand it if you think selection is all that matters: the process was driven by an initial combination of chance mutation, drift, and subsequent selection. As Thornton explained in a criticism of Behe,

In his posts about our paper, Behe’s first error is to ignore the fact that adaptive combinations of mutations can and do evolve by pathways involving neutral intermediates. Behe says that if it takes more than one mutation to produce even a crude version of the new protein function, then selection cannot drive acquisition of the adaptive combination.

This does not mean, however, that the evolutionary path to the new function is blocked or that evolution runs into a “brick wall,” as Behe alleges. If the initial mutations have no negative effect on the ancestral function, they can arise and hang around in populations for substantial periods of time due to genetic drift, creating the background in which an additional mutation can then yield the new function and be subject to selection. This is precisely what we observed in our studies of the evolution of the glucocorticoid receptor (GR).

In our 2007 paper in Science, we showed that multiple mutations were indeed required for the GR to evolve its specificity for the hormone cortisol; some of the mutations that trigger the change in function are deleterious if introduced in isolation, but others are “permissive”: they have no apparent effect on the function of the protein, but once they are in place the protein can tolerate the other mutations that shift and then optimize the new function.

Even in something as specific as the physiological function of a biochemical pathway, adaptation isn't the complete answer, and evolution relies on neutral or nearly neutral precursor events to produce greater functional complexity.

More like this

Geeze John Wilkins. Even 3rd graders know that the human genome contains approximatly 12,000 pseudogenes. Whats John going to try and tell us next? That Loop-mediated isothermal amplification is complex, frail and expensive? Or that the target sequence is amplified at a constant temperature using either two or three sets of primers and a monomerase with high strand displacement activity, when clearly it utilizes a polymerase. Geeze, were not that dumb John. Some people....

"complex traits are the product of selection?"

Right. They're not. They were magically constructed by a space-elf, or just spontaneously popped into existence overnight. No selection required.

Like I say, you'd fit in much better in the Discovery Institute.

@234

I suggest reading the post again. And again.

Seriously, PZ is really struggling with his criticism here. His claim is that "complexity is not usually the product of selection", but the best he can do is demonstrate a couple of cases of molecular evolution which, well, actually are the product of selection. PZ himself says:

"...the process was driven by an initial combination of chance mutation, drift, and SUBSEQUENT SELECTION." [emphasis added]

PZ is hunting strawmen here. Nobody in the EP field thinks that chance mutation and recombination have no role at all in the production of complexity. It's been well over twenty years since there has been debate about whether fitness must literally "increase incrementally at each step". That sounds more like a Creationist criticism of what they think evolutionists say than an actual criticism of what evolutionary biologists genuinely say.

It is suggestive that the not-quite counter examples PZ gives are from molecular biology. There's a certainly level of complexity involved in globins, say, but that's not really what people mean when they talk about complexity in the context of evolutionary *psychology*, is it? If PZ wants to argue that, say, monkey grooming behaviour is a result of random drift, that would be an interesting argument to read.

There are good and interesting criticisms of EP and its tendency to encourage "Just So" stories without proof, especially the way the ignorant use EP stories to "explain" temporary cultural beliefs as if they were normative biological imperatives. But this is not one of them.

By Steven D'Aprano (not verified) on 15 Dec 2012 #permalink

Nevertheless Natural Selection Is Always Involved Where Ever Complex Features Become Fixed in Populations (until proved otherwise).

By W. Benson (not verified) on 17 Dec 2012 #permalink

I think the assertion "complexity is not usually the product of evolution" is a grey sentence that depending on how much black and how much white it contets I could agree or not.

Mutation is random, and drift is the key process that spread that mutation through population. Latter selection could favor that mutation or not. All of this is true, and the relative importance of drift compared to other factors.

But affirming (or expressing in a way that seems to affirm) that complexity is not usually favored by evolution is simply false. Using one or one thosand of examples is irrelevant and leads to composition fallacy (the examples refer to some attributes of organisms, and not organisms as a whole, or even the whole ecosystem) and hasty generalization (what happens sometimes happens always).

Reality is what it is and could not be denied. Models should explain it, and not reality fits in models. Complexity has been favored throughout evolution. That's the fact. At the beginning there were only procaryotes (or whatever pre-procaryotes) and today there are much more complex organisms, with much more complex functions. Even if most actual biological mass are bacterial, there are more complexity in proportion to the origin, where "all were bacteria", and actual "most" does not equal to "all".

There is a simple justification which explains why evolution has favored complexity and why it could not have happened in another way. This is called the Second Law of Thermodynamics. All what happens, and evolution is still a process inside this all, does because it increased in one way or another the Entropy of the Universe (system+surroundings). "Chaos" can and in fact does create "order" in opposition to religious thoughts. If not we couldn't do something as simple as freezing water (layman's example). Creating order (reducing entropy) happens naturally because it increases entropy in the sorroundings in an higher degree, so the balance in the Universe is still positive. This justifies the emergence of life (order) from no-life (chaos) by natural ways and no need of FSM or The Pink Unicorn.

Complexity equals order in a fixed amount of materia. So yes, evolution, which is a natural phenomenon so it's regulated by natural laws (2nd Law Ther.) favors complexity. That's what happened, that's what happens, and it could not be in another way. True that step by step the issue is not so easy, and in a fixed and small amount of time chance would weight more than selection, but in the long run complexity wins. The long run does not imply every isolated characteristic, but the system (organisms, ecosystem) as a whole.

Affirming that evolution only cares about small and short-timed changes, where chance dominates, is simply false. In that case order, which implies complexity, could not have origininated from chaos, and life would have not happened. Evolution as a whole (materia-ecosystem, and time) does favor complexity. Saying otherwise is ignoring the facts and denying the natural laws of Physics.

There is also a correlation between Thermodinamic Entropy and Information Entropy, the second correlates (~gauges) the amount of information. Complexity increases the amount of contained information therefore entropy Information, therefore thermodynamic information (not that a more complex system has a higher thermodinamic entropy which is the opposite, but the energy cost needed (entropy pwoduced in the surroundings) needed for storing the amount of information in the system (genes in this case).

By Antonio Amo (not verified) on 19 Dec 2012 #permalink

A small detail. I cared about not defining concrete cases of complexity. All I said above referes as the whole complexity of an organism or even the ecosystem, and not particular, concrete cases of complexity in one property, organ, whatever. Sometimes yes, but not always necessarily in these cases. The whole is wll that matters.

P.S. Sorry if I made some mistake in grammar or vocabulary. Non-native speaker here.

By Antonio Amo (not verified) on 19 Dec 2012 #permalink